https://doi.or g/10.31449/inf.v48i9.3448 Informatica 48 (2024) 107–1 12 107 Argumentation-based Machine Learning for In consistent Knowledge Bases Nguyen Thi Hong Khanh Electric Power University , Hanoi, V ietnam E-mail: khanhnth@epu.edu.vn Keywords: belief mer ging, ar gumentation Received: February 19, 2021 In this paper , we intr oduce a new ar gumentation framework for belief mer ging. T o this end, a constructive model to mer ge possiblistic belief bases built based on the general ar gumentation framework is pr oposed. An axiomatic model, including a set of rational and intuitive postulates to characterize the mer ging r esult is intr oduced and several logical pr operties ar e mentioned and discussed. Belief mer ging is one of active r esear ch fields with a lar ge range of applications i n Artificial Intelligence. Most of the work in this r esear ch field is in the centralized appr oach, however , it is difficult to apply to interactive systems such as multi-agent systems. Povzetek: Vpeljan je ar gumentacijski okvir za združevanje pr epričanj, ki uporablja konstruktivni model za združevanje baz pr epričanj in vključuje nabor racionalnih in intuitivnih postulatov za karakterizacijo r ezultatov združevanja. 1 Intr oduction In recent years, Belief Mer ging, a research field study on the integration of the knowledge bases, has become an at- tractive research area in Artificial Intelligence. It is applied in a lar ge range of a reas such as Information Systems, Mul- tiagent Systems, Data Retrieval, and Distributed Systems. The advantage of belief mer ging approach is the richness of information we can obtain but its trade-of f is the incon- sistencies that we have to solve. In literature, there are two main approaches to deal with the inconsistencies arisen when we combine multiple information sources. In the first approach, we will try to adopt the incon- sistency in obtaining information source by improving the classical reasoning methods. One of typical instances of this idea is the family of paraconsistent logics [16, 9, 8]. This approach needs a simple operation to collect and store information from source, but it requires a highly computa- tional complexity reasoning operation. Unfortunately , the reasoning operation is more frequently used than another , thus this approach is only suitable for a specific class of ap- plications. In the second approach is using b elief mer ging in which we try to build a consistent information system from mul- tiple information sources. Precisely , from the given belief bases{ K 1 ,...,K n } we build a consistent belief baseK ∗ which best represents for these belief bases.There are two settings in this approach, the centralized and distributed ones. In centralized setting, belief mer ging is considered as an arbitration in which all belief bases are submitted to a mediator , and this mediator will decide which is the com- mon belief base. This is the main trend in belief mer ging with a lar ge range of works such as [20, 21]. Obviously , in this setting the mer ging result is depend on the mediator , the participating agents have to expose all their own beliefs and they are omitted in mer ging process. Therefore, it is dif ficult to apply to high interactive systems such as multi- agent systems. In the second setting, each mer ging process is consid- ered as a game in which participants step by step give their proposals until an agreement is reached. The first direc- tion in this setting is belief mer ging by negotiation with some typical works are as follows: a family of game-based mer ging operators[17], a two-stage belief mer ging process [10, 1 1], a bar gaining game solution [27] and a game model for mer ging stratified belief bases [19, 22, 23, 25, 26]. The second direction is belief mer ging by ar gumentation in which mer ging process is or ganized as a debate and par - ticipants uses their own beliefs and manipulates ar gumenta- tion skills to reach the agreement. T ypically , an ar gumenta- tion framework for mer ging weighted belief bases [15] and other framework for mer ging the belief bases in possibilis- tic logic by Amgoud et al. [3]. In [24], a general framework for mer ging belief bases by ar gumentation is introduced, however , the semantics of ar gumentation extensions are not mentioned and discussed. In this work, we propose a new ar gumentation frame- work for mer ging possibilistic logic bases. The contribu- tion of this paper is two-fold. First, we introduce a frame- work to mer ge possibilistic belief bases in which a general ar gumentation framework is applied in possibilistic belief bases to obtain meaningful results in comparison to other belief mer ging techniques for belief mer ging in possibilistic logic such as [3, 5, 4, 7, 18]. Second, an axiomatic model in- cluding rational and intuitive postulates for mer ging results is introduced and several logical properties are discussed. The rest of this paper is or ganized as follows: W e review about possibilistic logic in Section II . Belief mer ging for 108 Informatica 48 (2024) 107–1 12 N.T .H. Khanh prioritized belief bases by possibilistic logic framework is presented in Section III . Section IV and Section V introduce a general ar gumentation framework and a model to mer ge belief bases by this framework. Postulates for belief mer g- ing by ar gumentation and logical properties is introduced an discussed in Section VI . Some conclusions and future work are presented in Section VII . For the sake of representation, we consider the follow- ing example: A terrible environmental crisis, which cause mass fish deaths (a ), happened in the seabed in Middle of V ietnam. There are some opinions ordered in time series as follows: The public and scientists: The mass fish deaths (a ) are caused by the toxic spill disaster of a steel factory (b ): (b→ a ). Steel factory: W e have a modern waste water treatment system (c ), thus the water was cleaned before it was dis- char ged: (c,c →¬ b ). Communication agencies: The steel factory has imported hundreds of tons of chemical toxic (d ) and its under ground tube is put at wrong position (f ): (d,f ). The public and scientists: A diver has died (g ) with the symptom caused by toxin from water (b ): (g,b → g ). Steel factory: W e have imported chemical material to de- ter gent our tubes (d ) however the water was cleaned before it was dischar ged: (¬ (d→ b) ). Our under ground tube is in the right position and it has not been completed, thus it can dischar ge now: (¬ f ). Official A uthorities: There are two causes of mass fish deaths. It may be from chemical toxin (d ) or it may cause by algae bloom phenomenon (e ): (d→ a)∨ (e→ a ). W e have not yet had any clue about the relation between mass fish deaths and the dischar ge of steel factory . The public and scientists: The mass fish deaths cannot cause by the algae bloom phenomenon because there is no body of algae, water did not change color and fishes died at the bottom: (¬ e ). From the progression of events as above, we have the sets of beliefs as follows: K 1 : { b→ a,g,b → g, ¬ e} , K 2 : { c,c →¬ b, ¬ (d→ b), ¬ f} , K 3 : { d,f } , K 4 : { (d→ a)∨ (e→ a)} . 2 Possibilistic logic In this work, we consider a propositional languageL built on a finite alphabetP and common logic connectives in- cluding¬ , ∧ , ∨ , and→ . The classical consequence relation is⊢ . W e useΩ to denote a finite set of interpretations ofL . Givenω ∈ Ω ,ω |= ψ represents thatω is a model of the formulaψ . A possibilistic formula(ψ,α ) includes a propositional for - mula ψ and a weight α ∈ [0, 1] . A possibilistic be- lief base is a finite set of possibilistic formulas K = (ψ i ,α i )|i = 1,...,n . W e denoteK ∗ an associated belief base w .r .tK defined as follows:K ∗ ={ ψ i | (ψ i ,α i )∈ K} . Obviously , a possibilistic belief baseK is consistent ifK ∗ is consistent and vice verse . W e also denoteK andK ∗ set of all possibilistic belief bases and their associated belief bases, respectively . For each possibilistic belief baseK , the possibility dis- tribution ofK , denoted byπ K as follows: [13]∀ ω ∈ Ω π K (ω ) =    1 if∀ (ψ i ,α i )∈ K,ω |=ψ i 1− max{ α i : (ψ i ,α i )∈ K andω ⊭ ψ i } otherwise (1) Continuing Example 1. Suppose that K = { (a, 0. 8), (¬ c;0. 7), (b → a, 0. 6), (c;0. 5), (c→¬ b;0. 4)} . According to Definition 2, we can determine the possibility distribution forK as follows:π K (a¬ b¬ c) = 1,π K (abc) = 0. 6,π K (ab¬ c) = 0. 5,π K (a¬ bc) = 0. 3 , andπ K (¬ abc) = π K (¬ ab¬ c) = π K (¬ a¬ bc) = π K (¬ a¬ b¬ c) = 0. 2 Given a possibilistic belief base K and α ∈ [0, 1] , the α − cut ofK is denoted byK ≥ α and defined as follows: (K ≥ α = { ψ ∈ K ∗ | (ψ,β ) ∈ K,β ≥ α } ) . Similarly , a strict α − cut of K is denoted by K >α and defined as follows: (K >α ={ ψ ∈ K ∗ | (ψ,β )∈ K,β >α } ) . Possibilistic belief baseK 1 is equivalent to possibilistic belief baseK 2 , written asK 1 ≡ K 2 if and only ifπ K1 = π K2 . It is easy to prove thatK 1 ≡ K 2 if f for allα ∈ [0, 1] (K 1 ) ≥ α ≡ (K 2 ) ≥ α ) 2.1 Possibilistic infer ence The inconsistency degr ee of possibilistic belief baseK is as follows: Inc(K) =max{ α i :K ≥ α i is inconsistent} (2) The inconsistency degree of possibilistic belief base K is the maximal value α i such that the α i − cut of K is inconsistent. Conventionaly , if K is consistent, then Inc(K) = 0 . Given a possibilistic belief base K and (ψ,α )∈ K ,(ψ,α ) is a subsumption inK if: (K\{ (ψ,α )} ) ≥ α ⊢ ψ (3) Respectively ,(ψ,α ) is a strict subsumption inK ifK >α ⊢ ψ . W e have the following lemma [6]: If (ψ,α ) is a sub- sumption inK thenK ≡ (K\{ (ψ,α )} ) . Given a possi- bilistic belief baseK , formulaψ is a plausible consequence ofK if: K >Inc(K) ⊢ ψ (4) Given a possibilistic belief base K , formula (ψ,α ) is a possibilistic consequence ofK , denotedK⊢ π (ψ,α ) , if: - K >Inc(K) ⊢ ψ - α>Inc (K) and∀ β >α,K >β ⊬ ψ Ar gumentation-based Machine Learning… Informatica 48 (2024) 107–1 12 109 In any inconsistent possibilistic belief baseK , all formulas with certainty degrees smaller than or equal toInc(K) will be omitted in the inference process. Continuing Example 2, obviouslyK is equivalent to K ′ ={ (a, 0. 8), (¬ c, 0. 7), (b→ a, 0. 6), (c, 0. 5)} . Formula (c → ¬ b, 0. 4) is omitted because of Inc(K) = 0. 5 . W e have: - Plausible inferences ofK are¬ a,c → a,b → a,... - Possibilistic consequences ofK are(c→ a, 0. 7), (b→ a, 0. 6),... . 3 Belief merging by argumentation in possibilistic logic In this section, we consider an implementation of general framework above in order to solve the inconsistencies oc- cur when we combine belief bases (K 1 ,...,K n ) . Let us start with the concept of ar gument. Each ar gument is pre- sented as a double⟨ S,s⟩ , wheres is a formula andS is set of formulas such that: (1) S ⊆K ∗ , (2) S ⊢ s , (3) S is consistent andS is minimal w .r .t. set inclusion. S is the support ands is the conclusion of this ar gument. W e denoteA(K) the set of all ar guments built fromK . W e recall an ar gumentation framework in [2], it is ex- tended from the famous one proposed by Dung in [14]. An ar gumentation framework is a triple⟨A , R, ⪰⟩ in whichA is a finite set of ar guments, R is a binary relation repre- sented the relationship among the ar guments inA , and⪰ is a preorder onA×A . W e also use≻ to represent the strict order w .r .t⪰ . LetX,Y be two ar guments inX . - Y attacksX ifY ⪰ X andY RX . - IfY RX butX ≻ Y thenX can defend itself . - X set of ar gumentsA defendsX ifY attacksX then there always existsZ ∈A andZ attacksY . A set of ar guments A is conflict-free if ∄ X,Y ∈ A such thatXRY The attack relations among ar guments include undercut and rebut. They are defined as follows: Let ⟨ S,s⟩ and ⟨ S ′ ,s ′ ⟩ be ar guments ofA(K) . ⟨ S,s⟩ undercuts⟨ S ′ ,s ′ ⟩ if there exists p ∈ S ′ such that s ≡ ¬ p . Namely , an ar - gument is under undercut attack if there exists at least one ar gument in its support is attacked. Let⟨ S,s⟩ and⟨ S ′ ,s ′ ⟩ be ar guments ofA(K) . ⟨ S,s⟩ rebuts⟨ S ′ ,s ′ ⟩ if s ≡ ¬ s ′ . Informally , two ar guments rebut each other if their conclu- sions are conflict. In [1], the authors ar gued that each ar gument has a degree of influence. It allows us to compare ar guments to choose the best one. When the priorities of ar guments are explicit, the higher certain beliefs support, the stronger the ar gument is. The strength of the ar gument is defined as follows: The force of an ar gumentA = ⟨ S,s⟩ , denoted byforce(A) is determined as follows: force(A) =min{ α i :ψ i ∈ S and(ψ i ,α i )∈K} . (5) W e consider any aggregation operator⊕ satisfied the fol- lowing properties: (1) ⊕ (0,... 0) = 0 , (2) Ifα ≥ β then for alli = 1,...,n , then ⊕ (x 1 ,...,x i− 1 ,α,x i+1 ,...,x n ) ≥ ⊕ (x 1 ,...,x i− 1 ,β,x i+1 ,...,x n ) . Several common aggregation operators considered in liter - ature are maximum (Max ), sum (Σ ) and lexicographical order(GMax ). LetK = { K 1 ,...,K n } be a set ofn pos- sibilistic belief bases and A = ⟨ S,s⟩ be an ar gument in A(K) , then - ∀ ψ i ∈ S,K i ⊢ (ψ j ,a ji ),i = 1,...,n. - force(A) =min{⊕ (a j1 ,...,a jn )} . By the force of ar gument, we can compare ar guments as follows: Ar gumentX is preferred to ar gumentY , denoted byX ≻ Y ifforce(X)>force(Y) . GivenK ={ (¬ b∨ a, 0. 9), (b, 0. 7), (¬ d∨ a, 0. 6), (d, 0. 5)} , we have: K ={ (¬ b∨ a, 0. 9), (b, 0. 7), (¬ d∨ a, 0. 6), (d, 0. 5)} . W e have two ar guments related toa : - A 1 =<{¬ b∨ a,b} ,a>, - A 2 =<{¬ d∨ a,d} ,a>. However ,A 1 is preferred toA 2 becauseforce(A 1 ) = 0. 7 andforce(A 2 ) = 0. 5 . The inconsistence of a possibilistic belief base K i can be calculated from the force of inconsistent ar guments as follows: Let K be a possibilistic belief base and ⟨A (K),Undercut, ≻⟩ be an ar gumentation framework. Inc att (K) =max{ min(force(X),force (Y))| α i attA j } . (6) where att ∈ { undercut,rebut} . Let K 1 = { (a ∨ ¬ b;0. 9), (f;0. 9), (g;0. 8), (¬ d ∨ ¬ e;0. 5), (¬ e;0. 5), (d;0. 5) , (a ∨ ¬ d;0. 4), (¬ b ∨ g;0. 3), (a ∨ ¬ e;0. 3), (a;0. 2), (a ∨ ¬ d∨¬ e;0. 1)} , K 2 = { (c;0. 8), (¬ f;0. 8), (¬ b∨¬ c;0. 2), (¬ b∧ d;0. 3)} , and ⊕ be an aggregation function defined as follows: ⊕ (α,β ) =α +β − α.β . W e have: K ⊕ = { (a ∨ ¬ b ∨ c;0. 98), (c ∨ f;0. 98), (a ∨ ¬ b ∨ ¬ f;0. 98), (c∨ g;0. 96), (¬ f ∨ g;0. 96), ((a∨¬ b)∧ (a∨ ¬ b ∨ d);0. 93), ((¬ b ∨ f) ∧ (d ∨ f);0. 93), (a ∨ ¬ b ∨ ¬ c;0. 92), (¬ b∨¬ c∨ f;0. 92), (a∨¬ b;0. 9), (f;0. 9), (c∨ ¬ d ∨ ¬ e;0. 9), (c ∨ ¬ e;0. 9), (c ∨ d;0. 9), (¬ d ∨ ¬ e ∨ ¬ f;0. 9), (¬ e ∨ ¬ f;0. 9), (d ∨ ¬ f;0. 9), (a ∨ c ∨ ¬ d;0. 88), (¬ b∨ c∨ g;0. 88), (a∨¬ d∨¬ f;0. 88), (¬ b∨ 1 10 Informatica 48 (2024) 107–1 12 N.T .H. Khanh ¬ f ∨ g;0. 88), (a ∨ c ∨ ¬ e;0. 86), ((g ∨ ¬ b) ∧ (g ∨ d);0. 86), (a∨¬ e∨¬ f;0. 86), (a∨ c;0. 84), (¬ b∨¬ c∨ g;0. 84), (a ∨ ¬ f;0. 84), (a ∨ c ∨ ¬ d ∨ ¬ e;0. 82), (a ∨ ¬ d ∨ ¬ e ∨ ¬ f;0. 82), (g;0. 8), (c;0. 8), (¬ f;0. 8), ((¬ b ∨ ¬ e) ∧ (d ∨ ¬ e);0. 65), ((¬ b ∨ d) ∧ (d);0. 65), (¬ b ∨ ¬ c ∨ ¬ d ∨ ¬ e;0. 6), (¬ b ∨ ¬ c ∨ ¬ e;0. 6), (¬ b ∨ ¬ c ∨ d;0. 6), (a∨¬ b∨¬ c∨¬ d;0. 52), ((¬ b∨ g)∧ (¬ b∨ g∨ d);0. 51), ((a ∨ ¬ b ∨ ¬ e) ∧ (a ∨ d ∨ ¬ e);0. 51), (¬ d ∨ ¬ e;0. 5), (¬ e;0. 5), (d;0. 5), (¬ b∨¬ c∨ g;0. 44), (a∨¬ b∨ ¬ c∨¬ e;0. 44), ((a∨¬ b)∧ (a∨ d);0. 44), (a∨¬ d;0. 4), (¬ b∨ g;0. 3), (a∨¬ e;0. 3), (¬ b∧ d;0. 3), (a∨¬ b∨¬ c∨¬ d∨ ¬ e;0. 28), (a;0. 2), (¬ b∨¬ c;0. 2), (a∨¬ d∨¬ e;0. 1)} . W e have: Undercut = (A 11 ,A 32 ), (A 11 ,A 33 ), (A 32 ,A 11 ), (A 32 ,A 12 ), (A 32 ,A 16 ), (A 32 ,A 17 ) , (A 32 ,A 18 ), (A 32 ,A 19 ), (A 32 ,A 21 ), (A 32 ,A 22 ), (A 32 ,A 25 ), (A 32 ,A 28 ), (A 32 ,A 29 ) , (A 32 ,A 30 ) . W e have: Inc undercut (K ⊕ ) =max{ min(0. 9, 0. 8),min (0. 9, 0. 8), min(0. 8, 0. 9),min (0. 8, 0. 9), min(0. 8, 0. 9),min (0. 8, 0. 9), min(0. 8, 0. 9),min (0. 8, 0. 88), min(0. 8, 0. 88),min (0. 8, 0. 88), min(0. 8, 0. 86),min (0. 8, 0. 84), min(0. 8, 0. 82),min (0. 8, 0. 82)} = 0. 8 . Therefore, the inconsistency degree ofK ⊕ is 0.8. Now , we can define the belief mer ging by ar gumentation as follows: Let K = { K 1 ,...,K n } be a set of possibilistic belief bases. Belief mer ging operator is defined as follows: ∆ att ⊕ (K) = { ψ | (ψ,a ) ∈ K ⊕ ,a > Inc att (K ⊕ )} where att ∈ { indercut,rebut} . W e call ∆ att ⊕ the family of BMA ( Belief Mer ging by Ar gumentation ) operators. Con- tinuing Example 3, withatt = undercut and⊕ (α,β ) = α +β − α.β we have: ∆ att ⊕ (K) = {{ (a∨¬ b∨ c), (c∨ f), (a∨¬ b∨¬ f), (c∨ g), (¬ f∨ g), ((a∨¬ b)∧ (a∨¬ b∨ d)), ((¬ b∨ f)∧ (d∨ f)), (a∨ ¬ b∨¬ c), (¬ b∨¬ c∨ f), (a∨¬ b), (f), (c∨¬ d∨¬ e), (c∨ ¬ e), (c∨ d), (¬ d∨¬ e∨¬ f), (¬ e∨¬ f), (d∨¬ f), (a∨ c∨ ¬ d), (¬ b∨ c∨ g), (a∨¬ d∨¬ f), (¬ b∨¬ f∨ g), (a∨ c∨ ¬ e), ((g∨¬ b)∧ (g∨ d)), (a∨¬ e∨¬ f), (a∨ c), (¬ b∨¬ c∨ g), (a∨¬ f), (a∨ c∨¬ d∨¬ e), (a∨¬ d∨¬ e∨¬ f)} . 4 Postulates and logical pr operties W e recall thatK = { K 1 ,...,K n } is a finite set of possi- bilistic belief bases,AF s is an ar gumentation framework is determined fromK . Aggregation functionK ⊕ is defined as follows: K ⊕ :K n → K ∗ . The set of postulates is intro- duced as follows: (SYM) K ⊕ ({ K 1 ,...,K n } ) =K ⊕ ({ K π (1) ,...,K π (n) } ) , whereπ is a permutation in{ 1,...,n } . Postulate (SYM), sometimes called (ANON)[12], en- sures the equity of participants. It states that the result of an ar gumentation process should reflect the ar gu- ments of the participants rather than their identity . (CON) ∄ ψ ∈ L (K ⊕ ({ K 1 ,...,K n } ) ⊢ ψ ) ∧ (K ⊕ ({ K 1 ,...,K n } )⊢¬ ψ ) Postulate (CON) states that belief mer ging by ar gu- mentation should return a consistent result. (UNA) if K ∗ 1 ≡ ... ≡ K ∗ n then K ⊕ ({ K 1 ,...,K n } ) ≡ K ∗ 1 . Postulate (UNA) presents the assumption of unanim- ity . It states that if all participants possess the same set of beliefs, then this set of belief should be the result of ar gumentation process. Clearly , Postulate (UNA) is more general than postulate (IDN) and it also implies (IDN) which is defined as follows: (IDN) K ⊕ ({ K i ,...,K i } )≡ K ∗ i It states that if all participants have the same possibilis- tic belief base, then after the ar gumentation process, we should have the result as its associated belief base. (CLO) ∪ n i=1 B ∗ i ⊢K ⊕ ({ K i ,...,K i } ) Postulate (CLO) requires the closure of the result of ar - gumentation process. It states that any belief in ar gu- mentation result should be in at least some input belief base. (MAJ) if |{ K ∗ i ⊢ ψ,i = 1...n }| > n 2 then K ⊕ ({ K i ,...,K i } )⊢ ψ . Postulate (MAJ) states that if a belief is supported by the majority group of participants, it should be in the result of ar gumentation process. (COO) ifK ∗ i ⊢ ψ,i = 1...n thenK ⊕ ({ K i ,...,K i } )⊢ ψ . Postulate (COO) states that if a belief is supported by all participants, it should be in the result of ar gumen- tation process. W e have the following lemma: It holds that: - (UNA) implies (IDN); - (MAJ) implies (COO). Investigate the properties of belief mer ging operator de- fined in the previous section we have: Family of BMA operators satisfies the following postu- lates (SYM) , (CON) , (UNA) , and (CLO) . It does not satisfy(MAJ) . 5 Conclusion In this paper , a framework for mer ging possibilistic belief bases by ar gumentation is introduced and discussed. The key idea in this work is using the inconsistent degree as a measure together with the notion of undercut to construct an ar gumentation framework for belief mer ging. A set of pos- tulates is introduced and logical properties are mentioned Ar gumentation-based Machine Learning… Informatica 48 (2024) 107–1 12 1 1 1 and discussed. They assure that the proposed model is sound and complete. The deeper analysis on the set of pos- tulates and logical properties, and the evaluation of com- putational complexities of belief mer ging operators in this framework are reserved as future work. Acknowledgment The authors would like to thank Professor Quang Thuy Ha, T ran T rong Hieu and Knowledge T echnology Lab, Faculty of Information T echnology , VNU University of Engineer - ing and T echnology for expertise support. Refer ences [1] L. Amgoud and C. Cayrol. Inferring from incon- sistency in preference-based ar gumentation frame- works. International Journal of Automated Reason- ing , 29:125–169, 2002. [2] L. Amgoud and C. Cayrol. A reasoning model based on the production of acceptable ar guments. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence , 34:197–216, 2002. [3] L. Amgoud and S. Kaci. An ar gumentation framework for mer ging conflicting knowledge bases. International Journal of Appr oximate Reasoning , 45(2):321 – 340, 2007. Eighth European Conference on Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reason- ing with Uncertainty (ECSQARU 2005). [4] S. Benferhat, D. Dubois, S. Kaci, , and H. Prade. Pos- sibilistic mer ging and distance-based fusion of propo- sitional information. Annals of Mathematics and Ar - tificial Intelligence , 34(1-3):217–252, 2002. [5] S. Benferhat, D. Dubois, S. Kaci, and H. Prade. Pos- sibilistic mer ging and distance-based fusion of propo- sitional information. Annals of Mathematics and Ar - tificial Intelligence , 34:217–252, March 2002. [6] S. Benferhat, D. Dubois, H. Prade, and M. W illiams. A practical approach to fusing and revising prioritized belief bases. Pr oceedings of EPIA 99, LNAI 1695, Springer V erlag , page 222–236, 1999. [7] S. Benferhat and S. Kaci. Fusion of possibilistic knowledge bases from a postulate point of view . In- ternational Journal on Appr oximate Reasoning , page 33: 255–285, 2003. [8] J. Béziau. Paraconsistent logic from a modal view- point. J. Applied Logic , 3(1):7–14, 2005. [9] H. A. Blair and V . Subrahmanian. Special issue para- consistent logic programming. Theor etical Computer Science , 68(2):135 – 154, 1989. [10] R. Booth. A negotiation-style framework for non- prioritised revision. In Pr oceedings of the 8th Confer - ence on Theor etical Aspects of Rationality and Knowl- edge , T ARK ’01, pages 137–150. Mor gan Kaufmann Publishers Inc., 2001. [1 1] R. Booth. Social contraction and belief negotiation. Inf. Fusion , 7:19–34, March 2006. [12] J. Delobelle, A. Haret, S. Konieczny , J. Mailly , J. Rossit, and S. W oltran. Mer ging of abstract ar - gumentation f rameworks. In C. Baral, J. P . Del- grande, and F . W olter , editors, Principles of Knowl- edge Repr esentation and Reasoning: Pr oceedings of the Fifteenth International Confer ence, KR 2016, Cape T own, South Africa, April 25-29, 2016. , pages 33–42. AAAI Press, 2016. [13] D. Dubois, J. Lang, and H. Prade. Possibilistic logic. In Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Pr ogramming, D. Gabbay et al., eds , page 439– 513, 1994. [14] P . M. Dung. On the acceptability of ar guments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming and n-person games. Artificial Intelli- gence , page 77:321–357, 1995. [15] D. Gabbay and O. Rodrigues. A numerical ap- proach to the mer ging of ar gumentation networks. In M. Fisher , L. van der T orre, M. Dastani, and G. Gov- ernatori, editors, Computational Logic in Multi-Agent Systems , volume 7486 of Lectur e Notes in Computer Science , pages 195–212. Springer Berlin Heidelber g, 2012. [16] A. Hunter . Paraconsistent Logics , pages 1 1–36. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, 1998. [17] S. Konieczny . Belief base mer ging as a game. Jour - nal of Applied Non-Classical Logics , 14(3):275–294, 2004. [18] G. Qi, J. Du, W . Liu, and D. A. Bell. Mer ging knowl- edge bases in possibilistic logic by lexicographic ag- gregation. In P . Grünwald and P . Spirtes, editors, UAI 2010, Pr oceedings of the T wenty-Sixth Confer ence on Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence, Catalina Island, CA, USA, July 8-1 1, 2010 , pages 458–465. AUAI Press, 2010. [19] G. Qi, W . Liu, and D. A. Bell. Combining multi- ple prioritized knowledge bases by negotiation. Fuzzy Sets and Systems , 158(23):2535–2551, 2007. [20] N. Rescher and R. Manor . On inference from incon- sistent premises. Theory and Decision , 1:179–219, 1970. [21] P . Z. Revesz. On the semantics of theory change: arbitration between old and new information. In 1 12 Informatica 48 (2024) 107–1 12 N.T .H. Khanh 12th ACM SIGACT -SIGMOD-SIGART symposium on Principles of Databases , page 71–92, 1993. [22] T . T ran and Q. V o. An axiomatic model for mer ging stratified belief bases by negotiation. In N.-T . Nguyen, K. Hoang, and P . Jedrzejowicz, editors, Computa- tional Collective Intelligence. T echnologies and Ap- plications , volume 7653 of Lectur e Notes in Computer Science , pages 174–184. Springer Berlin Heidelber g, 2012. [23] T . H. T ran, N. T . Nguyen, and Q. B. V o. Ax- iomatic characterization of belief mer ging by negotia- tion. Multimedia T ools and Applications , pages 1–27, June 2012. [24] T . H. T ran, T . H. K. Nguyen, Q. Ha, and N. T . V u. Ar - gumentation framework for mer ging stratified belief bases. In Intelligent Information and Database Sys- tems - 8th Asian Confer ence, ACIIDS 2016, Da Nang, V ietnam, Mar ch 14-16, 2016, Pr oceedings, Part I , pages 43–53, 2016. [25] T . H. T ran, Q. B. V o, and R. Kowalczyk. Mer ging be- lief bases by negotiation. In Knowledge-Based and In- telligent Information and Engineering Systems - 15th International Confer ence, KES 201 1, Kaiserslautern, Germany , September 12-14, 201 1, Pr oceedings, Part I , pages 200–209, 201 1. [26] T . H. T ran, Q. B. V o, and T . H. K. Nguyen. On the belief mer ging by negotiation. In 18th International Confer ence in Knowledge Based and Intelligent Infor - mation and Engineering Systems, KES 2014, Gdynia, Poland, 15-17 September 2014 , pages 147–155, 2014. [27] D. Zhang. A logic-based axiomatic model of bar gain- ing. Artif. Intell. , 174:1307–1322, November 2010.