© Nova univerza, 2018 DIGNIT AS Revija za človekove pravice Slovenian journal of human rights ISSN 1408-9653 Rational Disagreement Targets Matjaž Potrč Article information: To cite this document: Potrč, M. (2018). Rational Disagreement Targets, Dignitas, št. 59/60, str. 235- 250. Permanent link to this doument: https://doi.org/ 10.31601/dgnt/59/60-17 Created on: 07. 12. 2018 To copy this document: publishing@nova-uni.si For Authors: Please visit http://revije.nova-uni.si/ or contact Editors-in-Chief on publishing@nova-uni.si for more information. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License. 235 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets 1 AbSTRAcT There are two implicitly present views about the targets of ra- tional disagreement. If one takes conciliation as a strategy con- cerning rational disagreement, then the target in the wide sense of the word is propositions. On the other hand, if one takes jud- gments to be targets of rational disagreement, then the accom- panying strategy is that of non-conciliation. This last strategy is closer to the nature of rational disagreement in terms of its phe- nomenology and rationality. Key words: rational disagreement, conciliation, non-conciliati- on, propositions, judgments Predmeti razumnega nestrinjanja POvzeTek Glede predmetov razumnega nestrinjanja obstajata dve stališči. Če razumemo spravljivost kot strategijo pristopa k razumnemu ne- strinjanju, so predmeti tega nestrinjanja – v najširšem pomenu te besede – propozicije. Če pa po drugi strani kot predmete razumne- ga nestrinjanja razumemo sodbe, je strategija, ki takšno nestrinjanje spremlja, odločnost. zadnja strategija je bližje naravi razumnega ne- strinjanja ter njegovi fenomenologiji in racionalnosti. Ključne besede: razumno nestrinjanje, spravljivost, odločnost, propozicije, sodbe 1 University of Ljubljana, matjaz.potrc@guest.arnes.si. Rational Disagreement Targets Matjaž Potrč 1 236 DIGNITAS n Filozofija Rational disagreement People often disagree. If arguments are involved, then the inte- resting ones are not emotionally heated squabbles, but an exchan- ge of views that are rationally supported and involve the parties’ respect for each other. When Putnam 2 mentions such a disagree- ment with his colleague, he says he holds him in great esteem as a human being and praises the qualities of his character. but he also states there are differences between them that cannot be bridged with respect to a certain issue. before coming back to rational di- sagreements in philosophy, we will take a quick look at the area of jurisprudence. Rational disagreement seems to be the basis of procedure in legal practice. What are the cases in question like? A presumption is that your fellow lawyer in a dispute is rational, i.e. that both you and him follow objectively verifiable procedures. but the two of you disagree about the truth of p. The prosecutor in penal law argues for p, whereas the defence argues for ¬p. both are rational, and they presume other parties to be rational as well. but once they have heard all the arguments of other parties, they still stick to their convictions. After having heard everything from the defence, the prosecutor continues to cling to their belief in p. Di- sagreement seems to be the basis of legal procedure. It also seems that non-conciliation – insisting on one’s views or positions and not abandoning them in the face of a challenge from the opposite player – is the rational choice in that area. Whatever the move of the other party, it does not seem to be a suitable rational choice to abandon one’s beliefs. On the contrary, a good lawyer has to stick to their guns and retain their beliefs, even though these may be shattered by the party that defends the opposite view in a proce- dural dispute. It also seems that legal procedure consists of assu- ming and playing roles so that deep down the judgment of the la- wyer, if there is one, disciplines the situation where the opposing positions guide a given dialectics. That is how I see the situation with legal discourse, although my knowledge mostly comes from legal cases as portrayed in several Tv series and in ‘whodunnits’. I will now switch to the case of philosophy with which I am slightly better acquainted. but before embarking on this, I need to stress the procedural embracing of non-conciliation in legal practice, which seems to be a bird of a different feather than conciliation’s 2 H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History. cambridge, 1981. 237 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets take on rationality that is mostly proposed by philosophers. How does this attitude come about in philosophy? I will consider this and then argue that non-conciliation is and should be a strategy appropriated by philosophers as well. Matters about rationality and about the phenomenology of peer disagreement will occu- py the centre of the exercise. cases of respectful philosophical disagreement, though, in contradistinction to legal cases, are not procedural and instead feature a commitment to one’s beliefs that are not necessarily needed for the legal procedure to be satisfied. Philosophical disagreements In order to understand rational disagreement and given that I work in this area, I will concentrate on the case of philosophy. A characteristic of philosophical work is that people are in dis- pute about practically any specific topic you may choose. Let me mention just one example off the top of my head. Some people think that there are essences of things, while others dispute this. Those who subscribe to essences are again in disagreement about whether these are to be searched for in concrete entities, such as this cat and that other kitten. Their opponents dispute this and see essences in something such as the idea of a cat given that, as they say, each particular cat may perish and because a cat as an entity is vague. On the other hand, the idea of a cat persists all along and during conceptual and empirical changes. At each car- ving of the joints there will be disagreement about which route to take. This seems to be the basis of philosophical endeavour. In contradistinction to legal practice, disagreement in philosophical discussion involves a substantive commitment and is thus not me- rely procedural. The difference between rational disagreement in the practice of law and in the practice of philosophy is that the practice of penal law opts for the irreducible difference of views to be ma- intained, whereas the now widely practiced and almost official procedure of philosophy also argues in defence of each particular view, but then mainly opts to give way to the peer with whom one is engaged in dispute so that the differences can be smoothed out. Philosophers tend to believe that this is required so that the de- mands of rationality are taken care of. I will argue that, as matters stand, the practice of rational disagreement in philosophy actual- 238 DIGNITAS n Filozofija ly does not end up in agreement but that the philosopher’s real work is to fight for their view, following their own best take on the epistemic evidential basis available to them. 3 This is supported by the dialectics of the philosopher’s judgment, which is rooted in benign incoherence. Judgment, and especially philosophical jud- gment, namely comes from a tension that arises between several forces producing it. Given that these forces are active from the background which is not transparent to the judger, and which is not explicitly there before their consciousness, there is some su- pport for this judgment that is not completely accessible to the judger. This applies to both of the parties involved in a rational disagreement. So the rationality of philosophical argumentation rests upon an insight hidden in the background that forms the judgment of each of the parties. The insight that supports each party’s judgment thus disciplines explicit argumentation which happens in a philosophical debate. Notice that philosophical di- sagreements are to some extent similar to moral disagreements where people feel they are involved in a procedure where quite a lot seems to be at stake. conciliation The main approach to the phenomenon of rational disagree- ment encountered today is that of conciliation. The presupposi- tion is that, if parties to a dispute are rational, they have to reali- se that no party has an advantage with respect to the opposite party. Accordingly, they will be happy to abandon their original beliefs in order for objective rationality requirements to be satis- fied so that one does not end up in the subjective arbitrariness of one’s belief or again in an outright contradiction with respect to the other party. The example that is usually given 4 involves two of us having lunch together, trying to calculate the amount of cash we are due to pay the waiter. I appreciate you as being rational and fairly good in matters of practical maths. You have the same respect for me. Now, we engage in the calculation. My result is $42, and your result is $46. We are ready to reconcile our views 3 T. Horgan and M. Potrč, Nonconciliation in Peer Disagreement: Its Phenomenology and Its Rational- ity, (forthcoming). 4 D. christensen, Disagreement as evidence: The epistemology of controversy, Philosophy Compass, 2009, 4/5, 756-75; D. christensen and J. Lackey, The Epistemology of Disagreement, Oxford 2013. 239 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets in view of our former opinions. However, we do not conclude that the right result would lie in the middle, namely $44. Instead, we abandon the initial results we arrived at and start calculating again. This is the form of conciliation that, as it seems, rationality requires from us. The idea is then that rationality further requires us to embrace the tactics of conciliation in other disputes as well, such as typical philosophical disputes such as the one mentioned about the essence of a cat. Rationality requires us, the reasoning goes, to abandon our beliefs and to reconcile. Here we see the surrounding symmetrical challenge: recognising you as a peer, I implicitly allow for my view not to be any better with respect to yours. And something similar goes for your view. Hence rationa- lity requires us, as already stated, to reconcile by abandoning our original beliefs. Non-conciliation However, from the practice of philosophical disputes we can see that people do not go for conciliation. They respect each other as able reasoners, that is true. but they do not move in the directi- on of conciliation. Instead, they go for non-conciliation, namely, they stick to their guns. In philosophy, you will very rarely see someone asserting that the essence is in specific cats then embra- cing the view that the essence of a cat resides in the idea of a cat. In most cases, people would prefer to stay with their former beli- efs and try to provide further arguments in support of their views in the face of a challenge by a peer. Their beliefs in the thesis they started with may be weakened as they listen to counter arguments. Yet, after a while, they search for their own arguments in defence of their thesis and so the strength of their belief increases. It is also quite unusual and not in line with the bulk of philosophical practice to opt for a middle-of-the-road solution: just what could someone who believes the essence is in particulars and someone else who believes the essence is in ideas find as a basis for com- mon ground? One may say that a non-conciliation strategy that guides philosophical cases of rational disagreement opts for a ver- sion of rationality that does not embrace exclusionary choices, and that it instead puts the stress on the ethics of belief 5 based on 5 W.k. clifford, The ethics of belief [1877]. In: T. Madigan, ed., The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays, Amherst 1999, 70–96; P. van Inwagen, It is Wrong, everywhere, Always, and for Anyone, to believe 240 DIGNITAS n Filozofija one’s evidential take on the matters at hand. It is a rationality dee- ply rooted in epistemological sensibility, leaning upon evidential, first-person commitments as the basis of this sensibility. Note that a commitment to some basic beliefs in the case of rational disagre- ement occurs in philosophically respectful disputes which does not happen in either procedural disagreements such as those il- lustrated by legal practices, nor in the case of differing estimates concerning a restaurant bill. No deep commitment to the content which is argued for is present in these cases, and that is exactly what usually happens in philosophical disagreements. Phenomenology What happens in a dispute involving rational disagreement? In order to consider the situation, one may have to take recourse to phenomenology, i.e. to the qualitative what-it’s-like take upon the practice of rational disagreement. A fact is that one treats one’s peer with whom one engages in a dispute as one’s global peer, i.e. as someone rationally respectable in the wide area under dis- pute. The same applies to the other party: they treat you as their global peer as well. This is part of the phenomenology of rational disagreement. Another part is that, by treating one’s adversary as a global peer, one does not treat them as one’s local peer. Namely, one is in disagreement with the party in relation to this specific question, although one respects them concerning their rationali- ty and their expertise in the wide area under dispute. Yet, in fact, one tends to treat the other party as one’s local inferior, and with respect to them, one experiences the feeling of one’s own local superiority. This is the phenomenology of peer disagreement, i.e. how one feels as one engages in rational disagreement in philo- sophy. I treat you as an able philosopher, and thus as my global peer. but because I accept that the essence of entities resides in concrete tokens, and realising that you see the essence inhabiting the abstract realm of ideas, I treat you as my local inferior. I have respect for you concerning the overall question of rationality. Ho- wever, concerning this specific question, you appear to me to be locally skewed. Phenomenology, as it seems, supports the non- conciliation strategy in rational disagreement. each of us conti- Something upon Insufficient evidence. In J. Jordan and D. Howard-Snyder, eds., Faith, Freedom and Rationality, Lanham, 1996, 137–153. 241 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets nues to stick to our guns, although all the arguments have been made and mutually fully considered. This is different from how conciliation views this area. The phenomenology is then that of local peerhood: one is supposed to treat one’s adversary in a phi- losophical dispute not simply as one’s global peer, but also as a lo- cal peer. This then gives one a reason to abandon one’s belief, and the same applies to one’s adversary as well. Yet such a conciliatory strategy does not seem to be supported by one’s phenomenology for the case of respectful philosophical disputes, contrary to dif- ferences in the restaurant bill maths case. In this last case, there is indeed no dispute that is committed to, the trait that enables con- ciliation and the abandoning of one’s belief, inviting both parties to go back to the drawing board and newly start their practices. The target of rational disagreement: propositions The main target of rational disagreement – does it centre on propositions or on judgments? The answer is that two deeply dif- ferent approaches are involved here. In short, the usual approach, aiming to justify beliefs that are supposedly involved in a rational disagreement, centres on propositions as its target. You and I then disagree about the proposition in question. As already mentioned, you assert p and I assert -p. What are propositions? A range of inter- pretations is available. They may be whatever is common to sen- tences of a kind, or again they may be material, or ideal. Further, they may reside in the mind, or in some objective state outside the mind. Whatever they are though, propositions have the following properties: they do not involve phenomenology, the rationality in accordance with them subscribes to explicit tractable reasoning and considers a breach of this as a case of a hard, malign contradic- tion. The propositional perspective is objective, proceeding from the third-person point of view. The embraced strategy is then that of conciliation. The beliefs involved are measured according to a probabilistic quantitative approach, they are supposed to come in degrees and they are then given the name of credences. epistemic justification is mainly that of beliefs with externalist reliabilism as a justificatory strategy. A justificatory environment is wide, local or global. The epistemic basis is explicit propositional content wi- thout any background involved. If principles are involved in the exercise, their mode and effectiveness are explicit. 242 DIGNITAS n Filozofija Judgments The judgmental approach is contrary to the propositional approach to rational disagreement. It is strange that this approach has not recently been appreciated for it goes along with the sepa- ration between the objective, propositional and psychologically rooted judgmental ways to proceed. However, if you think about it for a while, judgment is really the stuff involved in the pheno- menon of rational disagreement. The target of disagreement is then the judgment. A phenomenology is involved here, which as we have explained comes in local and global peerhood variants whereby the local variant is the feeling of one’s superiority. The rationality involved accepts the implicit background effectiveness of principles/attitudes and their benign constitutive incoherence. The perspective taken is the evidential, first-person kind. The stra- tegy embraced is non-conciliation. The beliefs involved are mea- sured according to their quality so that we talk about the strength of a belief, which comes down to one or zero beliefs, not to gra- des of beliefs. epistemic justification goes along with judgments, and a justificatory strategy is evidentialism. The justificatory en- vironment is narrow and transglobal. The epistemic basis is the implicit morphological content and background. The mode of the effectiveness of principles is indirect and implicit via chromatic illumination from the morphological background. Here is a sum- mary of the differences between the propositional and judgmen- tal approaches to rational disagreement: the target of disagreement proposition judgment phenomenology none global and local peerhood, with their combinations rationality explicit tractable reasoning or a hard, maligned contradiction implicit background effectiveness of principles/ attitudes and benign incoherence perspective taken third-person objective first-person subjective, evidential strategy embraced conciliation non-conciliation 243 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets beliefs quantitative probabilistic estimation of belief, credences strength of belief; quality epistemic justification of beliefs judgments justification strategy reliabilism evidentialism justificatory environment wide: local, global narrow: transglobal explicit or implicit epistemic basis propositional content, explicit, no background morphological content, background mode of effectiveness principles are present explicitly, their mode of effectiveness is explicit chromatic illumination by principles from the background, implicit Propositions or judgments The target of disagreement: propositions or judgments. The main issue here concerns the target of disagreement: are these propositions or are we dealing with judgments? However they may be interpreted, propositions are independent of mind: they may be Platonic ideal entities or even symbols of language of tho- ught. In any case, they differ from judgments in that they will not involve any psychological background implicit forces. We take it that rational disagreement deals with judgments: the parties invol- ved differ in their judgments on which propositions are correct or true, not with respect to the propositions. The main reason that we regard the target of rational disagreement, especially in philo- sophy, to be judgments is that these not only involve beliefs but beliefs that one is committed to, in some deep sense of the word. The question is whether the beliefs that are central to the discussi- on here go together with the propositions. The answer is that be- liefs may be well centred in propositions, yet this would succeed without any deep commitment, and this then puts the intrinsic re- lation of belief into question as well, allowing for conciliation and therewith the related abandoning of a belief. If a belief appears in a judgment, then the commitment to it and a non-conciliation strategy offers itself. 244 DIGNITAS n Filozofija Phenomenology: none, or once again local and global peerhood with their combinations A proposition-centred approach concerning rational disagre- ement will not really involve any phenomenology. This may be easily understood given that propositions, as already noted, do not involve any psychological ingredients. There may indeed be an attitude to a proposition. but, if one takes this route, a dispu- te in a rational disagreement is not about the attitude and more about the proposition. conversely, if judgments are the target of a rational disagreement then psychological ingredients are consti- tutively involved in whatever is under consideration. In this case, it is natural that phenomenology will be present. And phenome- nology is indeed involved, one considers the opponent as a glo- bal peer (which applies to both conciliation and non-conciliation strategies), or as a local inferior (this applies to the non-conciliati- on strategy only). Rationality: explicit tractable reasoning or a hard, malign contradiction on one side, and again the implicit background effectiveness of principles/ attitudes and benign incoherence on the other If the target of rational disagreement is a proposition, then the rationality involved tends to be conceived in the manner of ex- plicit tractable reasoning. Disputed propositions are an outcome of an inferential process. If the reasoning has some bumps in it, it is supposed that rationality is not really being pursued anymore so that one ends up with a hard, malign contradiction that tears the positions involved apart. Indeed, given that you argue for p and that your opponent argues for -p, this seems to be an outri- ght contradiction. Accordingly, proposition-centred rationality is exclusivist: either you follow the rules or you end up in contra- diction. However, if you decide judgment is the target of rational disagreement you will allow for a kind of incoherence given that the judgment is a result of several incompatible forces that end up being there in a unique hopper. but then you can take this incoherence to be of a weak and benign nature, and for that one allows for the assertive nature of a judgment. Further, a judgment 245 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets does not require the explicit following of rules since it rests upon the implicit background effectiveness of principles and rules that find themselves in the judgment-producing hopper. A judgment is actually rooted in weak benign incoherence because without the tension of several forces in the background it would be unable to enter the scene. The perspective taken: third-person objective or first-person subjective, evidential If a proposition is the target of rational disagreement, then the perspective taken is objective and from the point of view of a third person, say, who is not directly involved in the dispute. If a jud- gment is the target of rational disagreement, the perspective in- volved will instead be a subjective, first-person view. A judgment namely involves you directly, it is not made from an objective dis- tance. In fact, your judgment’s evidential support follows normati- ve justificatory perspective contextual parameters. 6 Moreover, on the other hand there are the normative justificatory perspective parameters of your peer. This pushes the situation in the direction of non-conciliation. The strategy embraced: conciliation or non-conciliation If a proposition is the target of rational disagreement, you will embrace a strategy of conciliation since you will try to avoid a malign kind of contradiction. If a judgment is your target, you will instead lean towards the strategy of non-conciliation. It is finally your judgment and you will normally try to adhere to it. This is especially important in view of the epistemic justification of your judgment because once an epistemic justification comes from the evidential sensitivity it will be difficult for you to share this episte- mic sensitivity with your peer. 6 M. Potrč and v. Strahovnik, Justification in context, Acta Analytica, 2005, 2, 91–104. 246 DIGNITAS n Filozofija beliefs: quantitative probabilistic estimation of belief, credences, or the strength of belief with its quality The propositional approach views propositions as being asses- sed by beliefs. but these beliefs are assessed through probabilistic estimation procedures so that beliefs themselves appear as partial beliefs, with the name of credences. In contrast, the judgmental approach takes beliefs to be one or zero matters. It does not allow for grades of belief, and instead goes with the strength of a belief. The strength depends upon evidence. We all believe that Aristotle was the teacher of Alexander the Great, and that bled is a town in Slovenia. Our belief in this latter assertion is stronger than that in the former assertion given that we have much more evidential support for the latter one. Strength of belief is a qualitative notion that cannot be reduced to quantitative degrees of belief. epistemic justification of beliefs or of judgments epistemic justification may target beliefs if we take the propo- sitional approach. epistemic justification may also be that of jud- gments. There will be different strategies for each of these. If a pro- position is the target of rational disagreement, then justification of the belief involved may be offered as coming in degrees. The belief will not be primarily evidentially committed to as happens in a judgment, and will instead come as a probability estimation of the matter involved. The justification of a belief in the case of a judgment will be more a matter of yes or no. One either judges p to be the case or one judges p not to be the case. Then one does not lean on estimated quantitative degrees of one’s belief. The be- lief that happens in judgments, as we have claimed, is a matter of one’s commitment. Justification strategy: reliabilism or evidentialism The justification strategy that goes hand in hand with proposi- tions will normally involve reliability, which is an externalist way to proceed. On the other hand, the justification strategy for a jud- 247 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets gment will tend to embrace evidentialism. 7 evidence is namely the justification you have for your judgment. If a belief targets a proposition, then it seems natural that the relation between that belief and proposition – that proposition being either an abstract entity or a concrete fact of the matter – will be externalist. This means that a belief will naturally target some external, causally or in some similar manner accessible reality. The justification will then follow that externalist route. If a belief is basically involved in a judgment, then the justification relation in question will be evidentialist for one’s commitment will move into the centre of at- tention. Justification in the case of a judgment relies on evidence, on whatever seems reliable to the one who is judging. The justificatory environment: wide local or global, or again narrow and transglobal The justificatory environment for propositions will be externa- list and thus wide. It will happen in the local environment first. Given that there will be counterexample cases such as fake barns, the external environment will then be taken more broadly as the global environment. If judgment is our departure, then the enviro- nment involved will be narrow and transglobal. This all goes well with evidence as the justificatory departure. One may start with re- liabilism as an externalist justification. Justification will then come through the direct relation to proposition as something objective – there will be an objective relation between the belief and pro- position as a form of an objective entity or state. However, once reliability encounters counterexamples the environment involved needs to be extended to the global and, further, to the transglobal one. 8 We started with a wide externalist relation, and finished up with a narrow qualitative evidentialist relation. 7 D. Henderson, T. Horgan and M. Potrč, Transglobal evidentialism-Reliabilism, Acta Analytica, 2007, 22, 281–300. 8 D. Henderson and T. Horgan, The Epistemological Spectrum: At the Interface of Cognitive Science and Conceptual Analysis, Oxford, 2011, M. Potrč, Justification Having and Morphological content, Acta Analytica, 2000, 24, 151–173. 248 DIGNITAS n Filozofija explicit or implicit epistemic basis: propositional content, explicit, with no background; or again morphological content with the background involved Propositions require an explicitly present epistemic basis whe- re the content involved is the propositional content without any background playing a major role in supporting it. If judgment is our departure, then the epistemic basis will be implicit. It will in- volve background morphological content. 9 This is indeed what seems to go together with the nature of a judgment. Notice that a judgment, as we have claimed, proceeds from a tension and this is the tension between several principles that prompt its coming into existence. The conflict between these principles, of which there are several, so that pluralism is involved, does not succeed in a judgment in a direct, explicit manner. The plurality of principles involved is effective from the psychological and normative back- ground that constitutes the judgment. Mode of effectiveness: principles are present explicitly, their mode of effectiveness is explicit; or again the chromatic illumination by principles from the background is implicit Propositions will be supported by principles that need to be explicitly present. If they are to be effective in embracing propo- sitions, principles must be explicitly present. belief then seems to centre on some independent reality in a direct manner, which then involves an estimation of degrees in which belief encounters this reality. If judgment is our departure, then principles will be involved in an implicit manner. They will be effective from the background so they will chromatically illuminate the holistic jud- gmental situation. We have claimed that a judgment is rooted in a tension between several principles that find themselves in a situ- ation. These principles are effective from the background of the 9 T. Horgan and M. Potrč, The epistemic Relevance of Morphological content, Acta Analytica, 2010, 25, 155–173; M. Potrč, Morphological content, Acta Analytica, 1999, 22, 133–149; T. Horgan and J. Tienson, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, cambridge, MA, 1996. 249 DIGNITAS n Rational Disagreement Targets judger’s cognitive ability and normative sensibility 10 (Foley 1993, Horgan and Potrč 2006), such that they provide the force in direc- tion towards the judgment by illuminating it from that backgro- und. In fact, if beliefs are taken to be targeting propositions then it is hard to understand just what leads to the phenomenon of rational disagreement. We take it that this phenomenon is rooted in the background implicit knowledge of the judger, with his ten- dency to remain with his initial view and to refine it. RefeRences William k. clifford, The ethics of belief [1877]. In: T. Madigan, ed., The Ethics of Belief and Other Essays. Amherst: MA: Prometheus 1999, 70–96. David christensen, Disagreement as evidence: The epistemology of controversy, Philosophy Com- pass, 2009, 4/5, 756–757. David christensen and Jennifer Lackey, The Epistemology of Disagreement, Oxford, OUP, 2013. Richard Foley, Working Without a Net: A Study of Egocentric Epistemology, Oxford, OUP, 1993. David Henderson and Terry Horgan, The Epistemological Spectrum: At the Interface of Cognitive Science and Conceptual Analysis, New York, OUP, 2011. David Henderson, Terry Horgan and Matjaž Potrč, Transglobal evidentialism-Reliabilism, Acta Ana- lytica, 2007, 22, 281–300. Terry Horgan and Matjaž Potrč, Particularist Semantic Normativity, Acta Analytica, 2006, 21, 45–61. Terry Horgan and Matjaž Potrč, The epistemic Relevance of Morphological content, Acta Analytica, 2010, 25, 155–173. Terry Horgan and Matjaž Potrč, Nonconciliation in Peer Disagreement: Its Phenomenology and Its Rationality, (forthcoming). Terry Horgan and John Tienson, Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology, cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1996. Matjaž Potrč, Morphological content, Acta Analytica, 1999, 22, 133–149. Matjaž Potrč, Justification Having and Morphological content, Acta Analytica 2000, 24, 151–173. Matjaž Potrč and vojko Strahovnik, Justification in context, Acta Analytica, 2005, 2, 91–104. Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History. cambridge, cambridge UP, 1981. Peter van Inwagen, It is Wrong, everywhere, Always, and for Anyone, to believe Something upon Insufficient evidence. In: J. Jordan J and D. Howard-Snyder, eds. Faith, Freedom and Rationality, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1996, 137–153. 10 R. Foley, Working Without a Net: A Study of Egocentric Epistemology, Oxford, 1993; T. Horgan and M. Potrč, Particularist Semantic Normativity, Acta Analytica, 2006, 21, 45–61. 250 DIGNITAS n Filozofija